Today when a periodical asks its readers a question, it
does so in order to collect opinions on some subject about which everyone
has an opinion already; there is not much likelihood of learning anything
new. In the eighteenth century, editors preferred to question the public
on problems that did not yet have solutions. I don't know whether or not
that practice was more effective; it was unquestionably more entertaining.
In any event, in line with this custom, in November 1784
a German periodical, Berlinische Monatschrift published a response
to the question: Was ist Aufklärung? And the respondent was Kant.
A minor text, perhaps. But it seems to me that it marks
the discreet entrance into the history of thought of a question that modern
philosophy has not been capable of answering, but that it has never managed
to get rid of, either. And one that has been repeated in various forms
for two centuries now. From Hegel through Nietzsche or Max Weber to Horkheimer
or Habermas, hardly any philosophy has failed to confront this same question,
directly or indirectly. What, then, is this event that is called the Aufklärung
and that has determined, at least in part, what we are, what we think,
and what we do today? Let us imagine that the Berlinische Monatschrift
still exists and that it is asking its readers the question: What is modern
philosophy? Perhaps we could respond with an echo: modern philosophy is
the philosophy that is attempting to answer the question raised so imprudently
two centuries ago: Was ist Aufklärung?
Let us linger a few moments over Kant's text. It merits
attention for several reasons.
-
To this same question, Moses Mendelssohn had also replied
in the same journal, just two months earlier. But Kant had not seen
Mendelssohn's text when he wrote his. To be sure, the encounter of
the German philosophical movement with the new development of Jewish
culture does not date from this precise moment. Mendelssohn had been
at that crossroads for thirty years or so, in company with Lessing.
But up to this point it had been a matter of making a place for Jewish
culture within German thought -- which Lessing had tried to do in
Die Juden -- or else of identifying problems common to Jewish
thought and to German philosophy; this is what Mendelssohn had done
in his Phadon; oder, Über die Unsterblichkeit der Seele. With
the two texts published in the Berlinische Monatschrift the
German Aufklärung and the Jewish Haskala recognize that they
belong to the same history; they are seeking to identify the common
processes from which they stem. And it is perhaps a way of announcing
the acceptance of a common destiny -- we now know to what drama that
was to lead.
-
But there is more. In itself and within the Christian
tradition, Kant's text poses a new problem.
It was certainly not the first time that philosophical
thought had sought to reflect on its own present. But, speaking schematically,
we may say that this reflection had until then taken three main forms.
-
The present may be represented as belonging to a
certain era of the world, distinct from the others through some
inherent characteristics, or separated from the others by some
dramatic event. Thus, in Plato's Statesman the interlocutors
recognize that they belong to one of those revolutions of the
world in which the world is turning backwards, with all the negative
consequences that may ensue.
-
The present may be interrogated in an attempt to
decipher in it the heralding signs of a forthcoming event. Here
we have the principle of a kind of historical hermeneutics of
which Augustine might provide an example.
-
The present may also be analyzed as a point of transition
toward the dawning of a new world. That is what Vico describes
in the last chapter of La Scienza Nuova; what he sees 'today'
is 'a complete humanity ... spread abroad through all nations,
for a few great monarchs rule over this world of peoples'; it
is also 'Europe ... radiant with such humanity that it abounds
in all the good things that make for the happiness of human life.'
[1]
Now the way Kant poses the question of Aufklärung
is entirely different: it is neither a world era to which one belongs,
nor an event whose signs are perceived, nor the dawning of an accomplishment.
Kant defines Aufklärung in an almost entirely negative way,
as an Ausgang, an 'exit,' a 'way out.' In his other texts on
history, Kant occasionally raises questions of origin or defines the
internal teleology of a historical process. In the text on Aufklärung,
he deals with the question of contemporary reality alone. He is not
seeking to understand the present on the basis of a totality or of
a future achievement. He is looking for a difference: What difference
does today introduce with respect to yesterday?
-
I shall not go into detail here concerning this text,
which is not always very clear despite its brevity. I should simply
like to point out three or four features that seem to me important
if we are to understand how Kant raised the philosophical question
of the present day.
Kant indicates right away that the 'way out' that characterizes
Enlightenment is a process that releases us from the status of 'immaturity.'
And by 'immaturity,' he means a certain state of our will that makes
us accept someone else's authority to lead us in areas where the use
of reason is called for. Kant gives three examples: we are in a state
of 'immaturity' when a book takes the place of our understanding,
when a spiritual director takes the place of our conscience, when
a doctor decides for us what our diet is to be. (Let us note in passing
that the register of these three critiques is easy to recognize, even
though the text does not make it explicit.) In any case, Enlightenment
is defined by a modification of the preexisting relation linking will,
authority, and the use of reason.
We must also note that this way out is presented by
Kant in a rather ambiguous manner. He characterizes it as a phenomenon,
an ongoing process; but he also presents it as a task and an obligation.
From the very first paragraph, he notes that man himself is responsible
for his immature status. Thus it has to be supposed that he will be
able to escape from it only by a change that he himself will bring
about in himself. Significantly, Kant says that this Enlightenment
has a Wahlspruch: now a Wahlspruch is a heraldic device,
that is, a distinctive feature by which one can be recognized, and
it is also a motto, an instruction that one gives oneself and proposes
to others. What, then, is this instruction? Aude sapere: 'dare
to know,' 'have the courage, the audacity, to know.' Thus Enlightenment
must be considered both as a process in which men participate collectively
and as an act of courage to be accomplished personally. Men are at
once elements and agents of a single process. They may be actors in
the process to the extent that they participate in it; and the process
occurs to the extent that men decide to be its voluntary actors.
A third difficulty appears here in Kant's text in his
use of the word 'mankind,' Menschheit. The importance of this
word in the Kantian conception of history is well known. Are we to
understand that the entire human race is caught up in the process
of Enlightenment? In that case, we must imagine Enlightenment as a
historical change that affects the political and social existence
of all people on the face of the earth. Or are we to understand that
it involves a change affecting what constitutes the humanity of human
beings? But the question then arises of knowing what this change is.
Here again, Kant's answer is not without a certain ambiguity. In any
case, beneath its appearance of simplicity, it is rather complex.
Kant defines two essential conditions under which mankind
can escape from its immaturity. And these two conditions are at once
spiritual and institutional, ethical and political.
The first of these conditions is that the realm of obedience
and the realm of the use of reason be clearly distinguished. Briefly
characterizing the immature status, Kant invokes the familiar expression:
'Don't think, just follow orders'; such is, according to him, the
form in which military discipline, political power, and religious
authority are usually exercised. Humanity will reach maturity when
it is no longer required to obey, but when men are told: 'Obey, and
you will be able to reason as much as you like.' We must note that
the German word used here is räsonieren; this word, which is also
used in the Critiques does not refer to just any use of reason, but
to a use of reason in which reason has no other end but itself: räsonieren
is to reason for reasoning's sake. And Kant gives examples, these
too being perfectly trivial in appearance: paying one's taxes, while
being able to argue as much as one likes about the system of taxation,
would be characteristic of the mature state; or again, taking responsibility
for parish service, if one is a pastor, while reasoning freely about
religious dogmas.
We might think that there is nothing very different
here from what has been meant, since the sixteenth century, by freedom
of conscience: the right to think as one pleases so long as one obeys
as one must. Yet it is here that Kant brings into play another distinction,
and in a rather surprising way. The distinction he introduces is between
the private and public uses of reason. But he adds at once that reason
must be free in its public use, and must be submissive in its private
use. Which is, term for term, the opposite of what is ordinarily called
freedom of conscience.
But we must be somewhat more precise. What constitutes,
for Kant, this private use of reason? In what area is it exercised?
Man, Kant says, makes a private use of reason when he is 'a cog in
a machine'; that is, when he has a role to play in society and jobs
to do: to be a soldier, to have taxes to pay, to be in charge of a
parish, to be a civil servant, all this makes the human being a particular
segment of society; he finds himself thereby placed in a circumscribed
position, where he has to apply particular rules and pursue particular
ends. Kant does not ask that people practice a blind and foolish obedience,
but that they adapt the use they make of their reason to these determined
circumstances; and reason must then be subjected to the particular
ends in view. Thus there cannot be, here, any free use of reason.
On the other hand, when one is reasoning only in order
to use one's reason, when one is reasoning as a reasonable being (and
not as a cog in a machine), when one is reasoning as a member of reasonable
humanity, then the use of reason must be free and public. Enlightenment
is thus not merely the process by which individuals would see their
own personal freedom of thought guaranteed. There is Enlightenment
when the universal, the free, and the public uses of reason are superimposed
on one another.
Now this leads us to a fourth question that must be
put to Kant's text. We can readily see how the universal use of reason
(apart from any private end) is the business of the subject himself
as an individual; we can readily see, too, how the freedom of this
use may be assured in a purely negative manner through the absence
of any challenge to it; but how is a public use of that reason to
be assured? Enlightenment, as we see, must not be conceived simply
as a general process affecting all humanity; it must not be conceived
only as an obligation prescribed to individuals: it now appears as
a political problem. The question, in any event, is that of knowing
how the use of reason can take the public form that it requires, how
the audacity to know can be exercised in broad daylight, while individuals
are obeying as scrupulously as possible. And Kant, in conclusion,
proposes to Frederick II, in scarcely veiled terms, a sort of contract
-- what might be called the contract of rational despotism with free
reason: the public and free use of autonomous reason will be the best
guarantee of obedience, on condition, however, that the political
principle that must be obeyed itself be in conformity with universal
reason.
Let us leave Kant's text here. I do not by any means propose
to consider it as capable of constituting an adequate description of Enlightenment;
and no historian, I think, could be satisfied with it for an analysis
of the social, political, and cultural transformations that occurred at
the end of the eighteenth century.
Nevertheless, notwithstanding its circumstantial nature,
and without intending to give it an exaggerated place in Kant's work,
I believe that it is necessary to stress the connection that exists between
this brief article and the three Critiques. Kant in fact describes
Enlightenment as the moment when humanity is going to put its own reason
to use, without subjecting itself to any authority; now it is precisely
at this moment that the critique is necessary, since its role is that
of defining the conditions under which the use of reason is legitimate
in order to determine what can be known, what must be done, and what may
be hoped. Illegitimate uses of reason are what give rise to dogmatism
and heteronomy, along with illusion; on the other hand, it is when the
legitimate use of reason has been clearly defined in its principles that
its autonomy can be assured. The critique is, in a sense, the handbook
of reason that has grown up in Enlightenment; and, conversely, the Enlightenment
is the age of the critique.
It is also necessary, I think, to underline the relation
between this text of Kant's and the other texts he devoted to history.
These latter, for the most part, seek to define the internal teleology
of time and the point toward which history of humanity is moving. Now
the analysis of Enlightenment, defining this history as humanity's passage
to its adult status, situates contemporary reality with respect to the
overall movement and its basic directions. But at the same time, it shows
how, at this very moment, each individual is responsible in a certain
way for that overall process.
The hypothesis I should like to propose is that this little
text is located in a sense at the crossroads of critical reflection and
reflection on history. It is a reflection by Kant on the contemporary
status of his own enterprise. No doubt it is not the first time that a
philosopher has given his reasons for undertaking his work at a particular
moment. But it seems to me that it is the first time that a philosopher
has connected in this way, closely and from the inside, the significance
of his work with respect to knowledge, a reflection on history and a particular
analysis of the specific moment at which he is writing and because of
which he is writing. It is in the reflection on 'today' as difference
in history and as motive for a particular philosophical task that the
novelty of this text appears to me to lie.
And, by looking at it in this way, it seems to me we may
recognize a point of departure: the outline of what one might call the
attitude of modernity.
I know that modernity is often spoken of as an epoch, or
at least as a set of features characteristic of an epoch; situated on
a calendar, it would be preceded by a more or less naive or archaic premodernity,
and followed by an enigmatic and troubling 'postmodernity.' And then we
find ourselves asking whether modernity constitutes the sequel to the
Enlightenment and its development, or whether we are to see it as a rupture
or a deviation with respect to the basic principles of the 18th century.
Thinking back on Kant's text, I wonder whether we may not
envisage modernity rather as an attitude than as a period of history.
And by 'attitude,' I mean a mode of relating to contemporary reality;
a voluntary choice made by certain people; in the end, a way of thinking
and feeling; a way, too, of acting and behaving that at one and the same
time marks a relation of belonging and presents itself as a task. A bit,
no doubt, like what the Greeks called an ethos. And consequently, rather
than seeking to distinguish the 'modern era' from the 'premodern' or 'postmodern,'
I think it would be more useful to try to find out how the attitude of
modernity, ever since its formation, has found itself struggling with
attitudes of 'countermodernity.'
To characterize briefly this attitude of modernity, I shall
take an almost indispensable example, namely, Baudelaire; for his consciousness
of modernity is widely recognized as one of the most acute in the nineteenth
century.
-
Modernity is often characterized in terms of consciousness
of the discontinuity of time: a break with tradition, a feeling of
novelty, of vertigo in the face of the passing moment. And this is
indeed what Baudelaire seems to be saying when he defines modernity
as 'the ephemeral, the fleeting, the contingent.' [2]
But, for him, being modern does not lie in recognizing and accepting
this perpetual movement; on the contrary, it lies in adopting a certain
attitude with respect to this movement; and this deliberate, difficult
attitude consists in recapturing something eternal that is not beyond
the present instant, nor behind it, but within it. Modernity is distinct
from fashion, which does no more than call into question the course
of time; modernity is the attitude that makes it possible to grasp
the 'heroic' aspect of the present moment. Modernity is not a phenomenon
of sensitivity to the fleeting present; it is the will to 'heroize'
the present .
I shall restrict myself to what Baudelaire says about
the painting of his contemporaries. Baudelaire makes fun of those
painters who, finding nineteenth-century dress excessively ugly, want
to depict nothing but ancient togas. But modernity in painting does
not consist, for Baudelaire, in introducing black clothing onto the
canvas. The modern painter is the one who can show the dark frock-coat
as 'the necessary costume of our time,' the one who knows how to make
manifest, in the fashion of the day, the essential, permanent, obsessive
relation that our age entertains with death. 'The dress-coat and frock-coat
not only possess their political beauty, which is an expression of
universal equality, but also their poetic beauty, which is an expression
of the public soul -- an immense cortège of undertaker's mutes (mutes
in love, political mutes, bourgeois mutes...). We are each of us celebrating
some funeral.' [3]
To designate this attitude of modernity, Baudelaire sometimes employs
a litotes that is highly significant because it is presented in the
form of a precept: 'You have no right to despise the present.'
-
This heroization is ironical, needless to say. The attitude
of modernity does not treat the passing moment as sacred in order
to try to maintain or perpetuate it. It certainly does not involve
harvesting it as a fleeting and interesting curiosity. That would
be what Baudelaire would call the spectator's posture. The flâneur,
the idle, strolling spectator, is satisfied to keep his eyes open,
to pay attention and to build up a storehouse of memories. In opposition
to the flâneur, Baudelaire describes the man of modernity:
'Away he goes, hurrying, searching .... Be very sure that this man
... -- this solitary, gifted with an active imagination, ceaselessly
journeying across the great human desert -- has an aim loftier than
that of a mere flâneur, an aim more general, something other
than the fugitive pleasure of circumstance. He is looking for that
quality which you must allow me to call 'modernity.' ... He makes
it his business to extract from fashion whatever element it may contain
of poetry within history.' As an example of modernity, Baudelaire
cites the artist Constantin Guys. In appearance a spectator, a collector
of curiosities, he remains 'the last to linger wherever there can
be a glow of light, an echo of poetry, a quiver of life or a chord
of music; wherever a passion can pose before him, wherever natural
man and conventional man display themselves in a strange beauty, wherever
the sun lights up the swift joys of the depraved animal.'
[4]
But let us make no mistake. Constantin Guys is not a
flâneur; what makes him the modern painter par excellence in
Baudelaire's eyes is that, just when the whole world is falling asleep,
he begins to work, and he transfigures that world. His transfiguration
does not entail an annulling of reality, but a difficult interplay
between the truth of what is real and the exercise of freedom; 'natural'
things become 'more than natural,' 'beautiful' things become 'more
than beautiful,' and individual objects appear 'endowed with an impulsive
life like the soul of their creator.' [5] For the attitude of modernity,
the high value of the present is indissociable from a desperate eagerness
to imagine it, to imagine it otherwise than it is, and to transform
it not by destroying it but by grasping it in what it is. Baudelairean
modernity is an exercise in which extreme attention to what is real
is confronted with the practice of a liberty that simultaneously respects
this reality and violates it.
-
However, modernity for Baudelaire is not simply a form
of relationship to the present; it is also a mode of relationship
that has to be established with oneself. The deliberate attitude of
modernity is tied to an indispensable asceticism. To be modern is
not to accept oneself as one is in the flux of the passing moments;
it is to take oneself as object of a complex and difficult elaboration:
what Baudelaire, in the vocabulary of his day, calls dandysme.
Here I shall not recall in detail the well-known passages on 'vulgar,
earthy, vile nature'; on man's indispensable revolt against himself;
on the 'doctrine of elegance' which imposes 'upon its ambitious and
humble disciples' a discipline more despotic than the most terrible
religions; the pages, finally, on the asceticism of the dandy who
makes of his body, his behavior, his feelings and passions, his very
existence, a work of art. Modern man, for Baudelaire, is not the man
who goes off to discover himself, his secrets and his hidden truth;
he is the man who tries to invent himself. This modernity does not
'liberate man in his own being'; it compels him to face the task of
producing himself.
-
Let me add just one final word. This ironic heroization
of the present, this transfiguring play of freedom with reality, this
ascetic elaboration of the self -- Baudelaire does not imagine that
these have any place in society itself, or in the body politic. They
can only be produced in another, a different place, which Baudelaire
calls art.
I do not pretend to be summarizing in these few lines either
the complex historical event that was the Enlightenment, at the end of
the eighteenth century, or the attitude of modernity in the various guises
it may have taken on during the last two centuries.
I have been seeking, on the one hand, to emphasize the extent
to which a type of philosophical interrogation -- one that simultaneously
problematizes man's relation to the present, man's historical mode of
being, and the constitution of the self as an autonomous subject -- is
rooted in the Enlightenment. On the other hand, I have been seeking to
stress that the thread that may connect us with the Enlightenment is not
faithfulness to doctrinal elements, but rather the permanent reactivation
of an attitude -- that is, of a philosophical ethos that could be described
as a permanent critique of our historical era. I should like to characterize
this ethos very briefly.
A. Negatively
-
This ethos implies, first, the refusal of what I like
to call the 'blackmail' of the Enlightenment. I think that the Enlightenment,
as a set of political, economic, social, institutional, and cultural
events on which we still depend in large part, constitutes a privileged
domain for analysis. I also think that as an enterprise for linking
the progress of truth and the history of liberty in a bond of direct
relation, it formulated a philosophical question that remains for
us to consider. I think, finally, as I have tried to show with reference
to Kant's text, that it defined a certain manner of philosophizing.
But that does not mean that one has to be 'for' or 'against'
the Enlightenment. It even means precisely that one has to refuse
everything that might present itself in the form of a simplistic and
authoritarian alternative: you either accept the Enlightenment and
remain within the tradition of its rationalism (this is considered
a positive term by some and used by others, on the contrary, as a
reproach); or else you criticize the Enlightenment and then try to
escape from its principles of rationality (which may be seen once
again as good or bad). And we do not break free of this blackmail
by introducing 'dialectical' nuances while seeking to determine what
good and bad elements there may have been in the Enlightenment.
We must try to proceed with the analysis of ourselves
as beings who are historically determined, to a certain extent, by
the Enlightenment. Such an analysis implies a series of historical
inquiries that are as precise as possible; and these inquiries will
not be oriented retrospectively toward the 'essential kernel of rationality'
that can be found in the Enlightenment and that would have to be preserved
in any event; they will be oriented toward the 'contemporary limits
of the necessary,' that is, toward what is not or is no longer indispensable
for the constitution of ourselves as autonomous subjects.
-
This permanent critique of ourselves has to avoid the
always too facile confusions between humanism and Enlightenment.
We must never forget that the Enlightenment is an event,
or a set of events and complex historical processes, that is located
at a certain point in the development of European societies. As such,
it includes elements of social transformation, types of political
institution, forms of knowledge, projects of rationalization of knowledge
and practices, technological mutations that are very difficult to
sum up in a word, even if many of these phenomena remain important
today. The one I have pointed out and that seems to me to have been
at the basis of an entire form of philosophical reflection concerns
only the mode of reflective relation to the present.
Humanism is something entirely different. It is a theme
or rather a set of themes that have reappeared on several occasions
over time in European societies; these themes always tied to value
judgments have obviously varied greatly in their content as well as
in the values they have preserved. Furthermore they have served as
a critical principle of differentiation. In the seventeenth century
there was a humanism that presented itself as a critique of Christianity
or of religion in general; there was a Christian humanism opposed
to an ascetic and much more theocentric humanism. In the nineteenth
century there was a suspicious humanism hostile and critical toward
science and another that to the contrary placed its hope in that same
science. Marxism has been a humanism; so have existentialism and personalism;
there was a time when people supported the humanistic values represented
by National Socialism and when the Stalinists themselves said they
were humanists.
From this we must not conclude that everything that
has ever been linked with humanism is to be rejected but that the
humanistic thematic is in itself too supple too diverse too inconsistent
to serve as an axis for reflection. And it is a fact that at least
since the seventeenth century what is called humanism has always been
obliged to lean on certain conceptions of man borrowed from religion
science or politics. Humanism serves to color and to justify the conceptions
of man to which it is after all obliged to take recourse.
Now in this connection I believe that this thematic
which so often recurs and which always depends on humanism can be
opposed by the principle of a critique and a permanent creation of
ourselves in our autonomy: that is a principle that is at the heart
of the historical consciousness that the Enlightenment has of itself.
From this standpoint I am inclined to see Enlightenment and humanism
in a state of tension rather than identity.
In any case it seems to me dangerous to confuse them;
and further it seems historically inaccurate. If the question of man
of the human species of the humanist was important throughout the
eighteenth century this is very rarely I believe because the Enlightenment
considered itself a humanism. It is worthwhile too to note that throughout
the nineteenth century the historiography of sixteenth-century humanism
which was so important for people like Saint-Beuve or Burckhardt was
always distinct from and sometimes explicitly opposed to the Enlightenment
and the eighteenth century. The nineteenth century had a tendency
to oppose the two at least as much as to confuse them.
In any case I think that just as we must free ourselves
from the intellectual blackmail of being for or against the Enlightenment
we must escape from the historical and moral confusionism that mixes
the theme of humanism with the question of the Enlightenment. An analysis
of their complex relations in the course of the last two centuries
would be a worthwhile project an important one if we are to bring
some measure of clarity to the consciousness that we have of ourselves
and of our past.
B. Positively
Yet while taking these precautions into account we must
obviously give a more positive content to what may be a philosophical
ethos consisting in a critique of what we are saying thinking and doing
through a historical ontology of ourselves.
-
This philosophical ethos may be characterized as a limit-attitude.
We are not talking about a gesture of rejection. We have to move beyond
the outside-inside alternative; we have to be at the frontiers. Criticism
indeed consists of analyzing and reflecting upon limits. But if the
Kantian question was that of knowing what limits knowledge has to
renounce transgressing, it seems to me that the critical question
today has to be turned back into a positive one: in what is given
to us as universal necessary obligatory what place is occupied by
whatever is singular contingent and the product of arbitrary constraints?
The point in brief is to transform the critique conducted in the form
of necessary limitation into a practical critique that lakes the form
of a possible transgression.
This entails an obvious consequence: that criticism
is no longer going to be practiced in the search for formal structures
with universal value, but rather as a historical investigation into
the events that have led us to constitute ourselves and to recognize
ourselves as subjects of what we are doing, thinking, saying. In that
sense, this criticism is not transcendental, and its goal is not that
of making a metaphysics possible: it is genealogical in its design
and archaeological in its method. Archaeological -- and not transcendental
-- in the sense that it will not seek to identify the universal structures
of all knowledge or of all possible moral action, but will seek to
treat the instances of discourse that articulate what we think, say,
and do as so many historical events. And this critique will be genealogical
in the sense that it will not deduce from the form of what we are
what it is impossible for us to do and to know; but it will separate
out, from the contingency that has made us what we are, the possibility
of no longer being, doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think.
It is not seeking to make possible a metaphysics that has finally
become a science; it is seeking to give new impetus, as far and wide
as possible, to the undefined work of freedom.
-
But if we are not to settle for the affirmation or the
empty dream of freedom, it seems to me that this historico-critical
attitude must also be an experimental one. I mean that this work done
at the limits of ourselves must, on the one hand, open up a realm
of historical inquiry and, on the other, put itself to the test of
reality, of contemporary reality, both to grasp the points where change
is possible and desirable, and to determine the precise form this
change should take. This means that the historical ontology of ourselves
must turn away from all projects that claim to be global or radical.
In fact we know from experience that the claim to escape from the
system of contemporary reality so as to produce the overall programs
of another society, of another way of thinking, another culture, another
vision of the world, has led only to the return of the most dangerous
traditions.
I prefer the very specific transformations that have
proved to be possible in the last twenty years in a certain number
of areas that concern our ways of being and thinking, relations to
authority, relations between the sexes, the way in which we perceive
insanity or illness; I prefer even these partial transformations that
have been made in the correlation of historical analysis and the practical
attitude, to the programs for a new man that the worst political systems
have repeated throughout the twentieth century.
I shall thus characterize the philosophical ethos appropriate
to the critical ontology of ourselves as a historico-practical test
of the limits that we may go beyond, and thus as work carried out
by ourselves upon ourselves as free beings.
-
Still, the following objection would no doubt be entirely
legitimate: if we limit ourselves to this type of always partial and
local inquiry or test, do we not run the risk of letting ourselves
be determined by more general structures of which we may well not
be conscious, and over which we may have no control?
To this, two responses. It is true that we have to give
up hope of ever acceding to a point of view that could give us access
to any complete and definitive knowledge of what may constitute our
historical limits. And from this point of view the theoretical and
practical experience that we have of our limits and of the possibility
of moving beyond them is always limited and determined; thus we are
always in the position of beginning again .
But that does not mean that no work can be done except
in disorder and contingency. The work in question has its generality,
its systematicity, its homogeneity, and its stakes.
(a) Its Stakes
These are indicated by what might be called 'the paradox
of the relations of capacity and power.' We know that the great promise
or the great hope of the eighteenth century, or a part of the eighteenth
century, lay in the simultaneous and proportional growth of individuals
with respect to one another. And, moreover, we can see that throughout
the entire history of Western societies (it is perhaps here that the
root of their singular historical destiny is located -- such a peculiar
destiny, so different from the others in its trajectory and so universalizing,
so dominant with respect to the others), the acquisition of capabilities
and the struggle for freedom have constituted permanent elements.
Now the relations between the growth of capabilities and the growth
of autonomy are not as simple as the eighteenth century may have believed.
And we have been able to see what forms of power relation were conveyed
by various technologies (whether we are speaking of productions with
economic aims, or institutions whose goal is social regulation, or
of techniques of communication): disciplines, both collective and
individual, procedures of normalization exercised in the name of the
power of the state, demands of society or of population zones, are
examples. What is at stake, then, is this: How can the growth of capabilities
be disconnected from the intensification of power relations?
(b) Homogeneity
This leads to the study of what could be called 'practical
systems.' Here we are taking as a homogeneous domain of reference
not the representations that men give of themselves, not the conditions
that determine them without their knowledge, but rather what they
do and the way they do it. That is, the forms of rationality that
organize their ways of doing things (this might be called the technological
aspect) and the freedom with which they act within these practical
systems, reacting to what others do, modifying the rules of the game,
up to a certain point (this might be called the strategic side of
these practices). The homogeneity of these historico-critical analyses
is thus ensured by this realm of practices, with their technological
side and their strategic side.
(c) Systematicity
These practical systems stem from three broad areas:
relations of control over things, relations of action upon others,
relations with oneself. This does not mean that each of these three
areas is completely foreign to the others. It is well known that control
over things is mediated by relations with others; and relations with
others in turn always entail relations with oneself, and vice versa.
But we have three axes whose specificity and whose interconnections
have to be analyzed: the axis of knowledge, the axis of power, the
axis of ethics. In other terms, the historical ontology of ourselves
has to answer an open series of questions; it has to make an indefinite
number of inquiries which may be multiplied and specified as much
as we like, but which will all address the questions systematized
as follows: How are we constituted as subjects of our own knowledge?
How are we constituted as subjects who exercise or submit to power
relations? How are we constituted as moral subjects of our own actions?
(d) Generality
Finally, these historico-critical investigations are
quite specific in the sense that they always bear upon a material,
an epoch, a body of determined practices and discourses. And yet,
at least at the level of the Western societies from which we derive,
they have their generality, in the sense that they have continued
to recur up to our time: for example, the problem of the relationship
between sanity and insanity, or sickness and health, or crime and
the law; the problem of the role of sexual relations; and so on.
But by evoking this generality, I do not mean to suggest
that it has to be retraced in its metahistorical continuity over time,
nor that its variations have to be pursued. What must be grasped is
the extent to which what we know of it, the forms of power that are
exercised in it, and the experience that we have in it of ourselves
constitute nothing but determined historical figures, through a certain
form of problematization that defines objects, rules of action, modes
of relation to oneself. The study of modes of problematization (that
is, of what is neither an anthropological constant nor a chronological
variation) is thus the way to analyze questions of general import
in their historically unique form.
A brief summary, to conclude and to come back to Kant.
I do not know whether we will ever reach mature adulthood.
Many things in our experience convince us that the historical event of
the Enlightenment did not make us mature adults, and we have not reached
that stage yet. However, it seems to me that a meaning can be attributed
to that critical interrogation on the present and on ourselves which Kant
formulated by reflecting on the Enlightenment. It seems to me that Kant's
reflection is even a way of philosophizing that has not been without its
importance or effectiveness during the last two centuries. The critical
ontology of ourselves has to be considered not, certainly, as a theory,
a doctrine, nor even as a permanent body of knowledge that is accumulating;
it has to be conceived as an attitude, an ethos, a philosophical life
in which the critique of what we are is at one and the same time the historical
analysis of the limits that are imposed on us and an experiment with the
possibility of going beyond them.
This philosophical attitude has to be translated into the
labor of diverse inquiries. These inquiries have their methodological
coherence in the at once archaeological and genealogical study of practices
envisaged simultaneously as a technological type of rationality and as
strategic games of liberties; they have their theoretical coherence in
the definition of the historically unique forms in which the generalities
of our relations to things, to others, to ourselves, have been problematized.
They have their practical coherence in the care brought to the process
of putting historico-critical reflection to the test of concrete practices.
I do not know whether it must be said today that the critical task still
entails faith in Enlightenment; I continue to think that this task requires
work on our limits, that is, a patient labor giving form to our impatience
for liberty.
Notes:
[1] Giambattista Vico, The New
Science, 3rd ed., (1744), abridged trans. T. G. Bergin and M. H. Fisch
(Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press, 1970), pp. 370, 372.
[2]
Charles Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life, trans. Jonathan Mayne
(London: Phaidon, 1964), p. 13.
[3] Charles Baudelaire, 'On the Heroism of Modern Life,' in The
Mirror of Art, trans. Jonathan Mayne (London: Phaidon, 1955), p. 127.
[4] Baudelaire, Painter, pp.
12, Il.
[5] Ibid., p. 12.
|