OPEN PAPER AS PDF
Introduction
Some people may not wish to read this
paper. It’s an attempt to make sense of my own past perpetration
of physical restraints and locked confinement of disabled Aboriginal
children. My nightmare scenario of writing this is that it will
do harm to people who’ve been subjected to such violence and
read it. If you have been subjected to physical restraints and locked
confinement, please know that this is the subject of the following
paper, and so you may or may not wish to read ahead. I could never
know for you whether or not you should proceed. On the other hand,
if, like me, you have perpetrated this kind of violence, then I
would encourage you to read it. If you feel defensive or otherwise
strongly, respond to what I write. I invite you to consider that
this may be a response that you can attend to ethically and politically
–and that it could be an important response that may not be
primarily or only about what I’ve written. Of course I could
never know this for you either.
Hannah Arendt wrote: “What I
propose … is nothing more than to think what we are doing”
(1998, p. 5), which I think fed her subsequent suggestion that a
more rigorous understanding of Adolf Eichmann’s account of
his thinking about what he was doing would have been politically
useful for us all. In this paper, I take her analysis of Eichmann’s
accounts and use it as starting points to explore resonances with
how I thought about what I was doing in the past as a residential
counsellor. I then briefly connect this to my work today as a social
work instructor and some pedagogical considerations that guide me
in that context.
Over ten years ago now, I worked as
a residential counsellor in a treatment centre. Elsewhere I’ve
critically explored this work on a more systemic and theoretical
level (Chapman, submitteda), but I’ve been hesitant to explore
my own use of violence directly, in physically restraining children
as young as eight and locking them up. I continue to struggle with
how I was able to do that.
I am not suggesting that other residential
counsellors or I can be equated with Eichmann. This would surely
do an injustice to many people in various ways. One of the perhaps
less obvious ways that it would do so is by taking away from the
particularity of the ways that real people navigate real contexts,
particularly when any one of us does real harm to any other (see
Ahmed, 1998, 2004, 2006; Arendt, 1964; Butler, 2004; Chapman, 2007,
2009, 2010; Derrida, 1995; Fellows and Razack, 1998; Foucault, 1994,
2006; Goodrum, Umberson, and Anderson, 2001; Hatzfeld, 2005; Heron,
2007; Jenkins, 1990, 2009; Mahmood, 2005; Neu and Therrien, 2003;
Wood, 2004). I approach Eichmann’s accounts, then, as particularly
embodied and contextualized narratives of personal ethical navigation,
as I understand Arendt to have done. I believe that we all navigate
our lives in ways that are available to us in part due to the structural
contexts in which we find ourselves and the stories we tell about
ourselves and the world. I believe this is a way to fruitfully approach
how anyone lives in this world and does things, whether it’s
you or I or Eichmann. Of course, not everyone ethically navigates
their life with equal effects on others. I believe, though, that
there’s something valuable in carefully attending to the ‘hows’
of such navigation – amongst those who do it very carefully,
those who do it with devastating consequences, and--like most of
us, probably--those who do it carefully sometimes and in certain
contexts and who also sometimes do it with harmful consequences.
This kind of analysis is distinct from an approach that imagines
violence and atrocities to be always committed by people entirely
unlike the rest of us, which I would suggest implicitly justifies
psychiatric and penal abuse and incarceration, as well as war. As
an alternative, I’m inviting curiosity about how someone becomes
an administrator of genocide, how someone else becomes a restrainer
and confiner of disabled Aboriginal children, and how we two very
different people—and the rest of us when we do harm—come
to accept hurting and oppressing others as normal or acceptable
and then go on with our lives. What makes this possible? What might
make it less likely to happen?
Why I believe it’s important
to take Eichmann’s account seriously
It’s easy for us to imagine that
Eichmann was simply a monster. And, of course, he was exactly that
in terms of what he did. But how he became what he became is another
question altogether (see Butler, 2004; Patel, 2009). According to
Arendt, this is more complicated than we might assume. She writes
(1964, p. 25), for example:
Eichmann pleaded: ‘Not guilty
in the sense of the indictment.’ [and so Arendt asked in
what sense he thought] he was guilty.… First of all, [he
claimed,] the indictment for murder was wrong: ‘With the
killing of Jews I had nothing to do [he stated]. I never killed
a Jew, or a non-Jew, for that matter – I never killed any
human being. I never gave an order to kill either a Jew or a non-Jew;
I just did not do it’…. Hence he repeated over and
over … that he could be accused only of ‘aiding and
abetting’ the annihilation of the Jews, which he declared
in Jerusalem to have been ‘one of the greatest crimes in
the history of Humanity’.
Elsewhere (Chapman, 2010), I explore
this dividing line he draws, using Guatemalan human rights activists’
distinctions between ‘material authors’ and ‘intellectual
authors’ of genocide (Jesús Tecu Osorio, cited in al
Nakba, 2008), in relation to other studies of people who have done
harm and the lines they draw to secure their own relative innocence
(Fellows and Razack, 1998; Goodrum, Umberson, and Anderson, 2001;
Hatzfeld, 2005; Heron, 2007; Wood, 2004). Here, however, it’s
the second point of his plea, alongside his statement that the annihilation
of the Jews was ‘one of the greatest crimes in the history
of Humanity,’ that interests me. His second point was this:
“The indictment implied not only that he had acted on purpose,
which he did not deny, but [that he had acted] out of base motives”
(Arendt, 1964, p. 25). He was, he claimed, ‘not guilty in
the sense of the indictment’ because the indictment assumed--as
I think we all tend to do when we hear of others’ violence--that
his motivation was clearly, simply, and unambiguously to do harm,
because he was a certain kind of person unlike the rest of us. In
relation to the idea that a given person ‘is’ a certain
kind of person, Michael White (2004a) has provided a very compelling
account of the distinction between what he calls ‘the folk
psychologies,’ which have always existed in all places and
all times, and the relatively recent, putatively scientific, and
Eurocentric ‘professional psychologies.’ It is only
in the latter, he suggests, that people are understood to be permanently
fixed as certain types of people, for example, as those who are
either good or bad, either sane or insane, either responsible or
irresponsible, etc. As Heron points out, this is particular to the
also relatively recent and Eurocentric liberal individualist understandings
of personhood (2007, p. 28), without which the professional psychologies
would have no ground whatsoever to have flourished. And Foucault
gives more detailed analyses of what made these forms of objectification
possible, describing certain developments as occurring “at
the level of what will soon be called psychology” (Foucault,
1970, p. 224). Further, he writes that these were not politically
neutral developments of theory or ideas:
we cannot say that the individual
pre-exists … the projection of the psyche, or the normalizing
agency. On the contrary, it is … through disciplinary mechanisms
that the individual appeared within a political system. The individual
was constituted insofar as uninterrupted supervision, continual
writing [i.e., of case notes], and potential punishment enframed
this subjected body and extracted a psyche from it. It has been
possible to distinguish the individual only insofar as the normalizing
agency has distributed, excluded, and constantly taken up again
this body-psyche…. The sciences of man, considered at any
rate as sciences of the individual, are only the effects of this
series of procedures (Foucault, 2008, p. 56; see also Chrisjohn,
Young and Mauran, 2006, and Davis, 2007, for the ways that this
continues to obscure power relations).
There is no reason other than habit for us to take for granted the
truth claims of these particular ways of understanding what humans
are. And I would like to suggest that a critique of the objectifications
of the professional psychologies coincides with the possibility
that Arendt’s account of Eichmann may be useful for all of
us in understanding how a person comes to become violent and oppressive
and especially how a person narrates or rationalizes this process.
Foucault writes:
many factors determine power. Yet
rationalization is also constantly working away at it. There are
specific forms to such rationalization. The government of [people]
by [people] – whether it is power exerted by men over women,
or by adults over children, or by one class over another, or by
a bureaucracy over a population – involves a certain type
of rationality [at the level, we might add, that has come to be
called psychology]…. Consequently, those who resist or rebel
against a form of power cannot merely be content to denounce violence
or criticize an institution…. What has to be questioned
is the form of rationality at stake. The criticism of power wielded
over the mentally sick or mad cannot be restricted to psychiatric
institutions; nor can those questioning the power to punish be
content with denouncing prisons as total institutions. The question
is: How are such relations of power rationalized? (1994, pp. 324-325).
It is this rationalization of relations
of power that seems to interest Arendt most in her careful study
of Eichmann’s own narratives. Arendt writes of what we most
easily assume to be his anti-Semitism, for example: “He ‘personally’
never had anything whatever against Jews; on the contrary, he had
plenty of ‘private reasons’ for not being a Jew hater.
[And then she adds] Alas, nobody believed him” (1964, p. 26).
This ‘alas’ is very significant to Arendt’s project.
I believe that she’s concerned that Eichmann is being misrepresented
for the sake of what we can learn from his example if what he says
is true (and even if it’s only partially true). I’m
following her lead in assuming that what he says is at least partly
true and in believing that we can all learn from the ways that he
accounts for the process of having ethically normalized and rationalized
his own perpetration of violence. Narrating it as ‘aiding
and abetting,’ rather than murder or genocide, surely played
some role. But how did he initially become comfortable with what
he called ‘aiding and abetting’ what he called ‘one
of the greatest crimes in the history of Humanity’? He says
he did not initially experience this as anything like acceptable:
when he was told of the Führer’s
order for the ‘physical extermination of the Jews,’
in which he was to play such an important role[, he says that]
he himself had ‘never thought of . . . such a solution through
violence,’ and he described his reaction [as follows]: ‘I
now lost everything, all joy in my work, all initiative, all interest;
I was, so to speak, blown out’ (Arendt, 1964, p. 31).
Of course we all know that this initial
response did not last.
How this resonates with how I came to normalize my own use of violence
First of all, let me say again that
I am not equating myself with Eichmann. When I use the term ‘resonance’
to describe a relationship between our respective processes of normalizing
and rationalizing violence, this should not be read as a making
of equivalencies. I am rather using this term along the lines of
what Tamboukou (2003) calls ‘dissonant harmony’--which
is to say a sense of some commonality, which is also very much ‘dissonant’
or distinct. I also relate to Jenkins’ (2009) description
of ‘parallel, political journeys’ by which he refers
to the resonance between his position as a therapist and that of
the men who perpetrate abuse that he works with: he’s suggesting
that his journey to be accountable for the real effects of his actions
on the men he works with and their families is ‘parallel’
or resonant with the journeys of the men he works with to become
accountable to their families’ experiences of them. He is
not suggesting that he is himself a perpetrator of domestic violence,
any more than I’m suggesting that I’m ‘the same
as’ Adolf Eichmann. I’m rather attending to very particular
ways that I can learn from Eichmann’s accounts of his own
process, allowing myself to ‘sit with’ what I feel as
resonance with his accounts, and using this as starting points for
my own reflexive exploration. This was precisely the methodology
of initially writing this paper.
I can still remember the specifics
of the first two restraints I ever did – and no others, in
the same kind of detail. I think these two continue to stand out
for me because, as Arendt says of Eichmann, my “conscience
[initially] functioned in the expected way” even if, relative
to the rest of my life, it functioned “within rather odd limits”
(Arendt, 1964, p. 95). Like Eichmann’s, this initial, expected,
conscientious response did not last.
I’d sought out a social services
job out of a sense of political commitment. I believed that working
with ‘disadvantaged’ youth was a way to make a difference
in the world – along the lines of something like global justice.
When I first started the job, I had no training or experience, but
I had a lot of ideas and enthusiasm, which were politically, rather
than individualistically, oriented. I imagined watching John Wayne
movies with the children and collectively critiquing their racism,
for example. And I imagined that doing so might be ‘therapeutic’
because of how I came into the job understanding what it meant to
be ‘disadvantaged’. But then I took on the training
regime of what I needed to learn to do my job (see also Chapman,
submitteda). And so instead of watching cowboy movies critically
and asking the children what they thought, I watched things like
‘Ten Things to do Instead of Hitting’ (Sunburst, 1995)
uncritically and then told the children what to do. One of the things
that my training regime entailed, for me, because of who I’d
always been, was ongoing concern about my ability to ‘set
limits’, ‘establish boundaries’ and generally
discipline and control. I had to learn to be ‘the adult’
in the relationship, even though I’d never had an adult like
that in my life. And one of the major things this entailed was to
physically restrain kids.
In fact, untrained and inexperienced,
I soon found out that I had basically been hired on as muscle, which
seemed like a joke really. I was also to be a ‘male role model’
to the kids, which was also a bit of a joke to me, but the concern
about male physical strength was explicitly stated. Before I was
ever expected to take the lead in education groups or counselling,
I took the lead in physical restraints. Because I was a man. Alongside
sighs of exasperation about there being no Aboriginal staff and
no serious efforts to address this, the centre had a strict policy
that half of the full time staff be male. White women who had worked
there casually for years were not hired, no Aboriginal people were
considered, and they took my effeminate University dropout masculinity
as the best they could do. I found myself with a job involving pay
and responsibility that was unparalleled amongst my peer group at
the time.
As I understood it then, I was actually
making a difference in the real lives of survivors of family and
colonial violence and getting trained and compensated to do so,
and so I was very much ‘elated’ about aspects my situation
(see Arendt, 1964, pp. 53-54, on Eichmann’s strategies for
achieving elation, which I address below). But I also had to physically
restrain children, which was initially incredibly emotionally complicated
for me and which nothing in my previous life had prepared me for.
I can remember that when I talked with friends and family, the restraints
were a major focus of early conversations. I would state my discomfort
about what I was doing, but somehow the self-centred story of the
perceived ridiculousness of my body having been chosen to do such
a thing often won out. This ‘my body’ completely ignored
my whiteness, ability and maleness and instead focused exclusively
on my effeminacy—the fact that it seemed funny to me that
a white male able body was considered appropriate to overpower disabled
Aboriginal children clearly shows my sense of disconnect from legacies
of colonization and eugenic institutionalization (See Chapman, submitteda).
‘Can you believe it,’ I would say, ‘they hired
me to do this? Some of those kids are bigger than I am and I’ve
never even been in a fight.’ This was funny to me, because
it was so incongruous with anything else I’d ever done or
known, but it was also incredibly disturbing to do these things.
And, perhaps even more disturbing, somehow I knew that this disturbance
was to be psychologically ‘worked through’ and ‘overcome’
rather than politically and ethically attended to.
Becoming perpetrator as a parallel,
political process to becoming self-blaming other
Of the Nazis, Arendt writes that, in
terms of affect and ethical self-governance,
the problem was how to overcome …
the animal pity by which all normal [people] are affected in the
presence of physical suffering. The trick used by Himmler –
who apparently was rather strongly afflicted with these instinctive
reactions himself – was very simple and probably very effective;
it consisted in turning these instincts around, as it were, in
directing them toward the self. So that instead of saying: What
horrible things I did to people!, the murderers would be able
to say: What horrible things I had to watch in the pursuance of
my duties, how heavily the task weighed upon my shoulders! (1964,
p. 106).
At the treatment centre, it was routinely
acknowledged that it was disturbing to physically restrain someone.
This was spoken about as an ‘unfortunate’ aspect of
the job. If only we could play games and have counselling sessions
all day, without the violence, without the time outs even, of course
we would all prefer that. But one of the things that came with ‘helping’
children who were ‘this damaged’, we said, was restraining
and confining. The idea that there could be a world without restraints
and locked confinement seemed clearly untrue, as evidenced by the
children we worked with, and so some of us had to do the ‘unfortunate’
work involved in ‘maintaining safety’ for them and others.
It’s not that we didn’t acknowledge that these restraints
were traumatic for the children being restrained or for other children
witnessing them, but we were the protagonists in the stories we
told and believed. Our violence was only ever a response to their
violence. The possibility of imagining their individual violence
as a response to our structural, epistemic, and individual violence--both
institutional/ableist and national/colonial/racist--was not available
to us. And so because they were the initiators of violence, as we
understood it, there was nothing we could do to prevent it (see
Butler, 2004). We had nothing to do with their violence, until it
erupted and our only role was to keep everyone safe. Even the room
where children were locked up, which usually followed a physical
restraint, was called a ‘safe room,’ which was clearly
an act of manipulating perception – but it’s hard to
locate the agent of that manipulation. As staff, I think we all
believed it. We perceived it. There was no safety without the safe
room, we said, ‘unfortunately’.
‘Unfortunately.’ It seems
to me that what was once an ethical and political ‘crisis
of conscience’ about what we were doing (Arendt, 1964, p.
104)--for me and perhaps for others--somehow gave way to this resigned
‘unfortunately,’ as if it was misfortune that placed
the children upon the path to the treatment centre rather than the
effects of real people’s concrete decisions and actions (see
Ahmed, 2004). As if it was misfortune that created the fact that
almost all of them were Aboriginal and almost all of us were white.
And, ‘unfortunately,’ someone had to ‘care for
them’ with all the sense of righteousness and self-sacrifice
that this implied. In fact, while I was there, all of the staff
went away on a retreat on ‘secondary post-trauma,’ that
is the trauma experienced as a result of exposure to others’
trauma. Doing what was clearly ‘group therapy,’ but
calling it ‘professional development,’ the purpose was
for us to explore the effects on us of the stories we heard in counselling
conversations, rather than the effects on us of restraining children,
but nevertheless, I can imagine a different ‘treatment’
of our feelings. Relative to the kids we worked with, our traumas
were much less significant, but they were nonetheless real. And
perhaps they could have instead been taken for what Arendt calls
‘instinctive reactions’ to both the painful experiences
the children told us about and the painful experiences we perpetrated.
But by psychologizing and thus depoliticizing our emotional and
at least potentially ethical and political struggles, we were actively
steered away from interrogating our own violence and the trauma
we were causing. In her paper for this PsychOUT conference earlier
today, Louise Tam (2010) cited Mitchell-Brody of the Icarus Project,
both of them using the following to question the pathologization
of people who are psychiatrized: “there is much in our world
to be angry, anxious or sad about.” I would like to suggest
here that the ‘normal’ or ‘instinctual’
or at least expected experiences of anger, anxiety and sadness that
staff experienced were psychologized and abnormalized in a ‘dissonant’
but harmonious way to the pathologization of the children we worked
with and others who are confined in similar closed sites. Taking
up Jenkins’ language differently than he uses it, I would
like to suggest that this was a ‘parallel, political journey’
– but it was not one of ‘becoming ethical’ in
the sense that ‘ethical’ sometimes means ‘moral.’
It was rather a process of becoming invested in a project of ethical
self-governance that would allow us to more comfortably occupy and
perpetuate our respective positions in systemic oppression.
I now consider my worry, guilt, and
anger about such things as important. The children I worked with
were pathologized of course, making our violence seem necessary,
but so too were workers’ struggles with perpetrating violence
psychologized and individualized, steering us away from approaching
these struggles as political or ethical concerns. When we restrained
children, we ‘debriefed’ newer staff afterwards, knowing
it was difficult to witness or participate in a restraint, and approaching
it as something to address through something like a ‘talking
cure’ with a predetermined destination: to accept perpetrating
violence as necessary.
The word ‘debrief,’ in
fact, as I understand it, is primarily otherwise used in military
contexts to work through having participated in military violence
and all that it entails–-and when ‘first world’
inhabitants come back from ‘development projects’ overseas.
In the latter, we can imagine that if the discomforts of coming
back to Canada after returning from Guatemala were approached as
‘ethical and political’ concerns to attend to, then
this would result in a more normative fundamental questioning of
geopolitical inequalities, starvation, war, and what Heron (2007)
calls ‘colonial continuities.’
In the treatment centre, our expected
and therefore ‘normal’ discomforts resulting from restraining
were differentiated from those of the children we worked with, implicitly
threatening staff with the identification of ‘emotionally
disturbed’ (or whatever) if we were unable to ‘work
through’ these initial discomforts. In fact, this was how
we as staff made sense of the ‘conscientious objector’
staff person I describe a few pages below: she was ‘not right’
or ‘not healthy enough’ to do the job or something along
those lines. Our discomforts as staff, however unpleasant, could
be worked through ‘normally,’ meaning without confinement
or restraint, proving that we were worthy of our freedom while the
kids we worked with, who seemed to ‘need’ these interventions,
were exceptionally, individually ‘disturbed.’
Resonant with this analysis, last year
I presented on a panel with Shaista Patel (2009) and Melissa Abbey
Strowger (2009). Shaista’s paper explored how ‘terror
suspects’ were described in popular press sources using discourses
of ‘madness,’ both erasing the possibility of understanding
‘terrorists’ as politically motivated and evoking a
longstanding tradition of incarcerating people who’ve committed
no crime because of their ‘psychological state’. Melissa’s
paper also looked at popular press sources, although her study was
of the ways that Americans’ anxiety about ‘the war on
terror’ was treated in these sources, anxiety that could,
at least potentially, be related to questioning the justice of American
military action. This anxiety was unlike the ‘madness’
of the ‘terror suspects’ that self-evidently required
incarceration. It was rather, according to some of her sources,
to be worked through using ‘relatively normal’ practices
often used in outpatient care for those not ‘requiring’
confinement, restraint, and so on: If you’re feeling anxious
about the war, here are some deep breathing exercises you could
do, or you might try positive aphorisms. ‘Parallel’
to one another, and certainly ‘politically,’ some people
are being psychologized in such a way to accept their implication
in war with less anxiety and uncertainty, and some are being psychologized
in such a way that the rest of us can accept their indefinite detention
and torture. This was a ‘parallel, political’ process
to what I understand took place at the treatment centre where I
worked. Both processes created discursive contexts within which
people could engage in ethical practices of self-formation (see
Mahmood, 2005). These ethical practices would, in turn (Foucault,
1990), reify the taken for grantedness of these discourses of rationality
and inevitability and, through them, people would constitute themselves
as agentively ‘willing’ to do the material acts also
necessary for the sustenance of systemic oppression, such as directly
perpetrating violence themselves or electing officials who choose
war, indefinite detention, and torture.
Furthermore, resonant with our staff
retreat to deal with secondary trauma, and also with newspapers
advocating deep breathing and affirmations for anxiety about war,
Arendt writes the following of what we might call Eichmann’s
‘positive self-talk’:
he had not forgotten a single one
of the sentences of his that at one time or another had served
to give him a ‘sense of elation.’ Hence, whenever,
during the cross-examination, the judges tried to appeal to his
conscience, they were met with ‘elation,’ and they
were outraged as well as disconcerted when they learned that the
accused had at his disposal a different elating cliché
for each period of his life and each of his activities. In his
mind, there was no contradiction between ‘I will jump into
my grave laughing,’ appropriate for the end of the war,
and ‘I shall gladly hang myself in public as a warning example
for all anti-Semites on this earth,’ which now, under vastly
different circumstances, fulfilled exactly the same function of
giving him a lift (1964, pp. 53-54; on this last point, see also
Ahmed, 2006, for a critique that may also pertain to my project).
And what was assumed in all this, what
held it all together, but which has no foundation, is an enduring
normal state, free of emotional discomfort, even in the face of
violence and oppression, that we and the children were both in the
process of being normalized toward, parallel to one another, but
distinctly. Following restraints, we ‘debriefed’ new
staff to help them feel at peace with perpetrating these forms of
violence, and then we ‘processed’ with the child who
had just been restrained, requiring them to accept ‘full responsibility’
for having individually caused the entire situation (see Jenkins,
1990). Any suggestion from a child that staff, other kids, or the
system played any part whatsoever in their individual choices or
actions would result in another fifteen minutes of locked confinement,
after which we would give them another opportunity to take ‘full
responsibility,’ unless some other duty delayed us, which
sometimes happened but was never our responsibility either. Their
discursively construed and structurally coerced ‘responsibility’
shaped their--and our--ethical and political possibilities of becoming
who we were becoming. We were all being trained to more fully inhabit
our respective positions within systemic oppression and to feel
fully responsible or not at all, accordingly.
The importance of alternative
accounts to processes of ethical self-formation
Significantly, we were not aberrational
in our normalization of our particular kind of violence. It is normative,
at least for those living in our time and place with systemic privilege,
to imagine the inevitability of the police, the army, psychiatric
confinement, prisons, and so on. I struggled initially with my role
in this place and practice, but it was not until I left the job
that I began to imagine a world without such places and practices.
“As Eichmann told it, the most potent factor in the soothing
of his own conscience was the simple fact that he could see no one,
no one at all, who actually was against the Final Solution. He did
encounter one exception, however, which he mentioned several times,
and which must have made a deep impression on him” (Arendt,
1964, p. 116).
In terms of encounters with exceptions,
critiques and alternatives, a difference between Eichmann and I
is that I had direct and sometimes very close relationships with
every one of the children I ever restrained. They said that what
we were doing was “contrary to morality”, they “appeal[ed]
to our feelings” (Arendt, 1964, p. 131) in deeds and words
of a wide variety of forms and intensities. But one of the things
that today I find so astounding in thinking back on this is that
all of those words and deeds only served to justify what we were
doing (see Chapman, 2009; Jenkins, 1990, 1991). The necessity of
our “Nonviolent Crisis Intervention” (Crisis Prevention
Institute, Inc., 2010) was proven by their violence (see Butler,
2004; but also Citizens Against Restraint, 2006). And even when
they asked about what we did in calm, articulate, curious ways,
or through tears, even then we were entirely sure about the morality
of what we were doing or at least its inevitability. This was just
how things were, and the only people who could change that were
the children: if they were never violent again, we would never be
violent. Simple.
Unlike Eichmann’s solitary exception,
I also had access to several critiques from the margins of the staff
team. These shook up my certainties more than the kids’ protests,
but it wasn’t until I left the job that my uncertainties really
flourished. At one point, I visited a former coworker who’d
moved away. She had been ‘night staff,’ which meant
that, according to local beliefs in the centre, she was less capable,
less knowledgeable, and so on, when it came to dealing with the
kids. Sometimes, if a child were upset, ‘day staff’
like me would stay late until the child was asleep, because it was
generally understood that ‘night staff’ didn’t
have the skills to deal with the kids when they were upset. They
didn’t do counselling and they didn’t do restraints,
so one of us had to be around if there might be a need for either.
The difference between night and day was a hierarchical one; we
were more skilled and competent. Although I was friendly with the
night staff and was only hired on as day staff because of my gender,
it never occurred to me that there might be alternative ways of
understanding this. But what this former night staff told me during
our visit was that they didn’t feel too incompetent to restrain
children. They were rather ethically opposed to it. She said something
like: “you day staff: a child cries and you go in and tell
them to stop or we’ll lock you up. Kids were sometimes upset
at night after all of you left. We read to them or just sat with
them or got them a cup of milk. That’s what you do when kids
are upset. You care for them. You don’t threaten to lock them
up. When any of you heard about it, all you could say is: they’re
manipulating you, don’t be so soft. But that’s what
you do when kids are upset.” These are responses I would much
prefer if I were upset, and it is certainly what I would want for
my son if he were, which invites all sorts of reconsideration of
the ways we made sense of parents and families. But sticking with
the issue of restraint and ethical navigation, night staff never
had to restrain kids, because of what they did, she said, implying
that we had to because of what we did. I think this significantly
influenced my decision to leave the job, although I wasn’t
sure I agreed with her. The very possibility that she could believe
it shook me up. And I was very surprised by her anger about it.
Why was she angry about how I was with the children? I was great
with them. I thought everyone knew that.
And then there was a woman who, in
the three years I worked there, was the single person who clearly
conscientiously objected to physical restraints. On her first day,
we restrained one of the children. She wasn’t involved, but
I knew that witnessing it would have been disturbing to her, so
I approached her to ‘debrief,’ again, depoliticizing
her response as psychological and requiring correction, rather than
ethical or political. She gathered up her stuff and said, “That
was horrible. I can’t do this,” and she left, tears
in her eyes.
I recall that staff mobilized non-professional
discourses of psychopathology--‘not right,’ ‘not
healthy enough,’ ‘too emotional,’ and similar
phrases in order to contain this person’s response as aberrational
and about her, rather than about what we had done. Perhaps we couldn’t
use terms from the professional psychologies--which we used liberally
in other contexts, because this would raise questions about how
she got hired in the first place, which might even unsettle the
normal/abnormal binary that we needed to feel okay about restraining
and confining other people’s children. So she was narrated
as occupying an interesting informal middle category that people
seem to use to situate abnormality within the margins of normality
and yet outside of professional intervention: phrases such as ‘nervous
breakdown’ or ‘not right.’ The implication was
something like this: maybe she just had to work on her positive
self-talk or her deep breathing or even see a private therapist,
and maybe then she’d be healthy enough to restrain children.
While not a coworker, a friend accompanied
me to the centre one day. One of the kids hung out of his window
to happily greet me and, in front of this friend, I ‘directed
him’ to go back into his room, knowing that he was surely
in his room for some disciplinary reason and shouldn’t be
hanging out of the window or generally enjoying himself. My friend
was shocked at how I spoke to him. The carefully crafted ‘adult/child
boundaries’ me, Chris the ‘child care counsellor,’
was not the Chris she knew. And again, I found her anger at me,
for how I had spoken to a child, very disruptive to my sense of
what was what. I had already set my departure in motion, but this
certainly heightened my sense that things weren’t right.
And when I drove away from that city,
I only then knew with complete certainty that I would never do those
things again.
Alternative accounts, ethics,
and accountability in the social work classroom
So what does this all have to do with
what I do today in social work classrooms? I’ll briefly outline
one example here (although I describe another aspect of this course
in Chapman, submittedb, and describe a social work ethics course
motivated by these same concerns and ideas in Chapman, 2010). I
designed and teach a full-year history of social work course at
Dalhousie University, in which I privilege accounts about the helping
professions from groups who are overrepresented as non-voluntary
clients. I want students to be able to perceive their future clients’
protests as something other than proof of our necessity and benevolence.
If a kid says, ‘you’re ruining my life,’ I want
them to think of the various histories we’ve read in which
at times well-intentioned experts and professionals really did ruin
people’s lives. To this end, we read First Nations, anti-racist,
mad movement, prison abolitionist, and disability studies histories
of professional helping, as well as reflexive critical accounts
of these histories written by helping professionals.
But what I also try to do in this course
is have students generate what Michael White called a ‘territory
of preferred identity’ (2004b, 2006) from which to situate
themselves in these critiques. This involves encouraging them to
relate to how the histories resonate in their own lives--not so
differently from what I’ve done here with Arendt’s Eichmann
– both in relation to the ways that they might have lived
some aspects of their life at the margins, as members of oppressed
communities, and also in relation to the privileges that they embody
or, at the very least, will embody as a paid professional social
worker, and perhaps in the ways that these two intersect, along
the lines of my particular manifestation of what I experienced as
an ‘alternative’ masculinity playing a role in obscuring
my recognition of my role in colonial, ageist and ableist domination.
Creating this ‘territory of preferred identity’ is,
I believe, what made it possible for me to write this exploration
of my own perpetration of violence against disabled Aboriginal children.
I can inhabit an ethical and political territory that is clear about
restraints and locked confinement being wrong, which allows me to
explore how I was so clear about it being right--or rather alright
even if ‘unfortunate’. Writing this wasn’t easy
for me to do, but I’m now able to perceive the associated
discomfort as a political aspect of my life – which can potentially
obscure my privilege and domination if I treat it as psychological,
and this allows me greater options in terms of what to do ethically
and politically with that discomfort. It is this increase of options
that I hope to facilitate amongst my students.
Conclusion
Whether or not there ought to be some
people in our communities who are paid to be ‘the helpers’
is an important question, although it’s one I haven’t
touched upon. But as long as there are professional helpers, and
likely there will continue to be professionals, even if we do abolish
this particular hierarchical structure, those who help need to be
aware of the likelihood that we will also harm. We need to become
better at becoming ethical and accountable, both when those who
we’re supposedly helping tell us that we’re doing harm,
and when our consciences do. My hope for this paper is that it might
assist others in this process of becoming ethical.
References
Abbey Strowger, M. (2009). Time after time: The ‘doings’
of anxiety’s appearance in the world. Paper presented at the
Society for Disability Studies Annual Conference, Tucson, Arizona.
Ahmed, S. (1998). Ethics. In Differences that matter: Feminist theory
and postmodernism (pp. 45-67). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ahmed, S. (2004). The contingency of pain. In The Cultural Politics
of Emotion (pp. 20-41). New York: Routledge.
Ahmed, S. (2006). The non-performativity of anti-racism. Borderlands
E-journal, 5 (3)
http://www.borderlands.net.au/vol5no3_2006/ahmed_nonperform.htm
al Nakba, T. (2008). The forgotten
spirits of Rabinal. Available: http://upsidedownworld.org/main/guatemala-archives-33/1442-guatemala-the-forgotten-spirits-of-rabinal
Arendt, H. (1964). Eichmann in Jerusalem.
New York: Viking Press.
Arendt, H. (1998). The Human condition.
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Butler, J. (2004). Precarious life.
New York: Verso.
Chapman, C. (2007). Dilemmas about
‘taking responsibility’ and cultural accountability
in working with men who have abused their female partners. The International
Journal of Narrative Therapy and Community Work, 4, 58-62.
Chapman, C. (2009). Self-reflexive
critique and fostering communities of support in education for social
change. Spaces/Places: Exploring the Boundaries of Adult Education.
28th Annual Conference Proceedings of the Canadian Association for
the Study of Adult Education, Ottawa, ON, pp. 326-328. Available
online under ‘Roundtables’: http://www.oise.utoronto.ca/CASAE/cnf2009/OnlineProceedings-2009/CASAE2009
Proceedings TOC.html
Chapman, C. (2010). Using our everyday
ethical transgressions as starting points for social justice education.
Canadian Association for the Study of Adult Education, Montréal,
PQ. To be published in the archive of 2010 Conference Proceedings
at: http://www.oise.utoronto.ca/CASAE/cnfmain/maincnf.html
Chapman, C. (submitteda). Colonialism,
disability, and possible lives: The residential treatment of children
whose parents survived Indian residential schools.
Chapman, C. (submittedb). Resonance,
intersectionality, and reflexivity in critical pedagogy (and qualitative
research).
Chrisjohn, R., Young, S., & Maraun,
M. (2006). The circle game: Shadows and substance in the Indian
Residential School experience in Canada. Penticton, B.C.: Theytus
Books.
Citizens Against Restraint (2006)
Belief statement and position paper. Available online: http://community-2.webtv.net/cibra7/CITIZENSAGAINST/
Crisis Prevention Institute, Inc. (2010)
Nonviolent Crisis Intervention © training program. Available
online: http://www.crisisprevention.com/program/nci.html
Davis, A. (2007). How does change happen?
Available: http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Pc6RHtEbiOA&feature=related
Derrida, J. (1995). The gift of death.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Fellows, M. L., & Razack, S. (1998).
The race to innocence: Confronting hierarchical relations among
women. Journal of Gender, Race and Justice, 1, 335-352.
Foucault, M. (1970). The order of things:
An archaeology of the human sciences. New York: Vintage Books.
Foucault, M. (1990). The history of sexuality, volume 1. New York:
Vintage Books.
Foucault, M. (1994). ‘Omnes et
singulatim’: Toward a critique of political reason. In Power:
Essential works of Foucault, vol. 3 (pp. 298-325). New York: The
New Press.
Foucault, M. (2006). The hermeneutics
of the subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-1982.
New York: Picador.
Foucault, M. (2008). Psychiatric power:
Lectures at the Collège de France, 1973-1974. New York: Picador.
Goodrum, S., Umberson, D., & Anderson,
K. (2001). The batterer’s view of the self and others in domestic
violence. Sociological Inquiry, 71(2), 221-40.
Hatzfeld, J. (2005). Machete season:
The killers in Rwanda speak. New York: Picador.
Heron, B. (2007). Desire for development:
Whiteness, gender, and the helping imperative. Waterloo: Wilfred
Laurier University Press.
Jenkins, A. (1990). Invitations to
responsibility: The therapeutic engagement of men who are violent
and abusive. Adelaide: Dulwich Centre Publications.
Jenkins, A. (1991). The Intervention
with violence and abuse in families: The inadvertent perpetuation
of irresponsible behavior. Australian and New Zealand Journal of
Family Therapy, 12(4) 186-195.
Jenkins, A. (2009). Becoming ethical:
A parallel, political journey with men who have abused. Dorset:
Russell House Publishing.
Mahmood, S. (2005). The politics of
piety: The Islamic revival and the feminist subject. Princeton:
Princeton University press.
Neu, D., & Therrien, R. (2003).
Accounting for genocide: Canada’s bureaucratic assault on
Aboriginal people. Halifax: Fernwood.
Patel, S. (2009). Encountering the terrorism of ‘madness’:
The nation’s normal race to the culture of categories. Paper
presented at the Society for Disability Studies Annual Conference,
Tucson, Arizona.
Sunburst (1995). Ten things to do instead
of hitting. Valhalla: Sunburst Visual Media.
Tam, L. (2010). How a counter-discourse
to the psychopathology of ‘obsessions’ departs from
the trope of ‘mad genius’: An autoethnographic study
of relationality from ‘local to universal.’ Paper presented
at PsychOUT: A Conference for Organizing Resistance Against Psychiatry,
Toronto, Ontario.
Tamboukou, M. (2003). Genealogy/Ethnography:
Finding the Rhythm. In M. Tamboukou, M. and S. J. Ball (Eds.) Dangerous
Encounters: Genealogy and Ethnography (pp. 195-216). New York: Peter
Lang.
White, M. (2004a). Folk psychology
and narrative practice. In Narrative practice and exotic lives:
Resurrecting diversity in everyday life (pp. 59-118). Adelaide:
Dulwich Centre Publications.
White, M. (2004b). Narrative therapy:
New modalities of practice. Truro, Nova Scotia.
White, M. (2006). Responding to children
who have experienced significant trauma: A narrative perspective.
In M. White and A. Morgan Narrative therapy with children and their
families (pp. 85-98). Adelaide: Dulwich Centre Publications.
Wood, J. (2004). Monsters and victims:
Male felons’ accounts of intimate partner violence. Journal
of Social and Personal Relationships, 21(5), 555-576.
|