![]() |
|||
Last Call for Harold Innis In a time when communications media loom very large, and we get what seems to me pretty shabby, shallow interpretations of them, it is nice to go back to Harold Innis. He took a technological approach to the analysis of historical and economic issues, in part to supplement and counter the devotion to sheer statistics and what he called “accountancy,” which seemed to dominate the profession even then. But it seems to me that Innis’ interest in a technological form of explanation grew out of a deeper soil, intellectually and autobiographically. In the preface to his final book, The Bias of Communications, he says all of what follows is by way of a response to a question by his professor of philosophy, James Ten Brooke, when Innis himself was an undergraduate. The question was, “Why do we attend to the things to which we attend?” I consider this question of Ten Brooke’s stunningly subversive. It is enough to interrupt almost anyone’s life at any point if you seriously ask it, and I take Innis’ allusion to it seriously. I propose to treat it as a genuine preface to his thought on the subject of communications. Where was Innis at the point in his life when he posed it to himself, or rather, to what had he been attending all his adult and professional life? To economic history, in short. I take Innis to be looking back on his entire life of effort and achievement and saying, What was that about? Why did I pay such attention to these questions of economic history, along with history in general, and Canadian economic history in particular? The answers he gives are quite sweeping and unexpected, and I do not intend to go through them in detail here. But I can say that he pins the blame for his – and our – concern with history itself on the effects of the biases of the technologies of communications which through time brought us to the current moment. In a sense you can say then that Innis uses his skill as a historian to identify the sources of the concern with history itself. But he also unleashes a critique of the mentality that takes history seriously. I think it is fair to say he regrets that mentality and having spent most of his life inside it. I am saying, in other words, that I do not see Innis’ final phase – his writings on communications – as an extension of the rest of his career; it was not, for example, simply an application of the theory of staples to the area of communications, as Marshall McLuhan proposed in his introduction to the book. In my opinion, Innis’ ideas on communication are a radical undercutting of the kind of thinking that marked the rest of his career. I do not think it would be right to say they are a rejection of his earlier writings; it is more a matter of walking away from the things that concerned him in them. The owl of Minerva takes flight only at dusk, Hegel wrote and Innis quoted; consider that this refers to Innis’ own wisdom coming only at the end of an illustrious and, by all conventional standards, successful intellectual career. There is a deeply existential quality to this turn in Innis’ life. Take, for instance, his embrace of the Oral Tradition
over the Written Tradition, the two main categories in Innis’ theories
of communication. We are not talking television versus computers or the
Internet: this is the Oral versus Written Tradition. A “tradition”
as a medium of communication. And then he opts for oral, the man who had
been probably more successful than any other Canadian within the written
tradition as it is known in our society. He had written many lauded books;
he was part of the tradition, but here he more or less dissociates himself
from it and dumps on it. Let me add that what Innis meant by the Oral
Tradition was not chit-chat: talks shows would not qualify. He meant an
oral discourse that was elitist and intellectual, but an intellectual
elitism transmitted and expanded mainly through face-to-face dialogue
between intellectual equals and their disciples. Furthermore, he did not
exclude a written component from the Oral Tradition; he wrote that “the
mixture of the oral and the written traditions in the writings[!] of Plato
enabled him to dominate the history of the west.” (One might make
the same point about the Talmudic tradition in Judaism which, though eventually
written down, managed to preserve in its very layout on the page a sense
of ongoing dialogue and a continuing invitation to it.) At any rate, Innis
came to the conclusion that “creative thought” was “dependent
on the oral tradition.” Writing is too fast, it is too unnuanced
compared to the complexity of speech. What it means to be human is to
speak and listen, to interact with others – and wisdom and insight
emerge in that social context. Writing and individual scholarship are
a dilution and “dumbing down” of basic human function; they
may be more efficient, in some respects, in creating Intellectual “product,”
but at a cost to the human and mental processes involved. This may seem
a little hard to take as you make your way through Innis College, attending
lectures or reading in the library; all around you people are working
in offices, preparing papers and books, and reading the work of others.
And, after all, I did sit down and write this paper. Take Innis’ emphasis on Time in these later writings, for an indication of how thorough his critique is, how self-critical, even self-lacerating. Innis associated predominantly oral cultures with what he called a sense of control over Time; while written cultures tended to do better in exercising control over Space. This is a difficult area – even for Innis’ later writings, but all I want to stress at the moment is that Innis included a preference for values associated with Time rather than Space in his self-described “bias” in favour of the Oral Tradition – and that what he meant by Time was not the same thing as History. Quite the contrary. Time, in the sense Innis uses it, is the opposite of History. History is what has obliterated the sense of time, of enduring values and underlying verities. History is not about Time, and History as a discipline is based on the breakdown of the sense of Time in an age in which Space, that is, spatial perceptions and space-based values, predominate, in which Time has been distorted into a succession of moments, as it were, “spatialized,” a process which began, according to Innis, with Leibniz (who took Space as a basic category) then Hegel and Marx, who are also not about Time, but about History. Time is about endurance, values that endure and underlie changes and discontinuities. Historicism, which Innis called “almost entirely a product of the 19th century,” marked the victory of “history over philosophy and science.” If this does not count as a repudiation of what Innis had spent his life doing, I don’t know what would. Finally, let us look directly at his treatment of media.
I do not believe the term itself actually appears in Innis’ writing;
he deals with one particular medium of communication or another, and its
biases. But to put Innis’ sense of media in focus, let me return
for a moment to the situation in the present. A striking phenomenon of
our time, it seems to me, is the emergence of Noam Chomsky as a formidable
media critic, especially among youth and students – that is, those
who have grown up with the mass media. To many of them, Chomsky is a kind
of cult figure. I know young people who do not bother watching the news;
they just wait to read Chomsky on the news. The Canadian film about him,
Manufacturing Consent, has become a kind of cult classic akin to The Rocky
Horror Picture Show. Now what I think is really interesting about the
emergence of Chomsky as the model of a media critic is that he is almost
entirely uninterested in media per se. You get the sense he nearly never
watches television or goes to a movie, and when he does he pays close
attention to the message and very little to the medium. What he is almost
exclusively concerned with is content in media, especially news media.
He is doing content analysis – more precisely, analyzing propaganda.
That it comes through one medium or another is fairly indifferent to him.
Propaganda is propaganda; he could just as well be analyzing the original
source of the term, the Catholic church of the late Middle Ages. Now compare
to this the mavens of media reality: Nicholas Negroponte of MIT’s
Media Lab, Wired magazine, television shows like CITY’s Media TV,
Newsworld’s Future World, or CBC’s Undercurrents – what
you find is preoccupation with the formal qualities of the medium and
little analysis of content. Moses Znaimer, for instance, likes to say
television is about flow not show, it is about process, not content. So
you get an analysis of the effect of form which yields sheer form, and
absolves any content from being of concern to the analysis. You see this kind of sensationalizing mentality even
in discussions about media and media technology themselves, as in statements
by media maven John Perry Barlow about computers or the Internet –
or whatever – being the most transforming technological breakthrough
since the discovery of fire; or Znaimer’s milder, more Canadian
assertion that television is the most important communications development
in 500 years. What might have intrigued Innis is not which breakthrough
was more stunning, but where does this mentality of sensational breakthroughs
come from altogether? One follows another with monotonous predictability.
If you take a step back, the whole mindset can seem a little embarrassing;
it is not impossible to imagine a society in which sensational breakthroughs
and firsts are not constantly being declared. Where does such a need,
such a mentality, come from? Innis answers that the technologies of communications
themselves have engendered a sort of breakthrough-mongering, which extended
even to the attitude toward new technologies. I think that his analysis
of the sensationalizing nature of media has stood the test of time since
his death. In our time, it is more prominent than ever: wars followed
by scandals followed by supermarket openings or the introduction of a
new pro-sports franchise, each one covered apocalyptically, ever swifter,
ever more unconnected. I do not think Innis and Chomsky are in the same
camp on this matter, but I think they both stand apart from the deliberately
technical and content-draining approach to media which contemporary media
experts tend to practise. An interesting analogue is Michel Foucault, who also immersed himself in empirical data and studies, yet who stands clearly, and intended to, as a figure in the history of philosophy. In Foucault’s own terms, he too was absorbed in the positivity of knowledge, in mastering and then questioning those positivities at their root, using them to ask why we attend to the things we do. And if it seems surprising to turn philosophical and abstruse in the wake of all that data and research, Foucault writes that no one should find it strange that by this route he has come to ask the profound and troubling philosophical questions that matter today, and also is “unable not to ask them.” “Only those who cannot read,” says Foucault, “will be surprised that I have learned such a thing more clearly from Cuvier (biology), Bopp (philology), and Ricardo (economics) than from Kant or Hegel.” Innis might say he learned to ask those questions more clearly by way of his studies of the fur trade and the fisheries than from political science or philosophy – that is, learned which questions matter today, and became unable not to ask them. “All empirical knowledge,” wrote Foucault, “provided it concerns man, can serve as a possible philosophical field in which the foundation of knowledge, the definition of its limits and in fact the truth of all truth must be discoverable.” In this light, you start to find it strange not that researchers like Foucault and Innis come to these questions by this route, but that so many manage not to do the same. It is part of Foucault’s call to awake from what he called “the anthropological sleep” of the past two centuries; that is, as I understand it, the mystifications and ambivalences occasioned by the scientific approaches and disciplines of our time. This is the same sleep from which, I believe, Innis too was trying to awaken himself at the end, by questioning the ground of our experience in the light of the values that underlie it, asking where they came from, and passing judgment on them. It is simultaneously ethical and epistemological. This kind of thing is not easily adaptable to serve the superficial needs of any era or interest group. It does not lend itself to reconciling you to the way things are or celebrating the status quo; it makes you deeply uneasy about how things are and how you are within them; it asks why you attend to the things to which you have attended all your life. It does not screen out the personal, social, or human elements of experience. It is hard to avoid those elements in Innis’ final writings. They arise from a need, an intellectual or even an existential need. They involve a quest for wisdom based on a brave querying of what he had done with his life and to some extent what we, in the sense of our civilization, have done with our lives . . . none of which, by the way, would likely endear you to the computer industry that places its ads in Wired magazine or endows Negroponte’s Media Lab at MIT. I would like to conclude by raising some questions about the small matters of the relation between thought and action, and between thought and society. I do this partly because I have distinguished between what I see as some shallowly ideological notions and visions of technology and that of Innis, which I admire. I also raise this question because I come from a background – the 1960, Marxism and so forth – which more or less took for granted the ideological/social role of all ideas and systems of thought – “If you’re not part of the solution, then you’re part of the problem,” etc. If at the end of his career Harold Innis was ready to throw into doubt and re-examine everything to which he had devoted his life as a scholar and historian, as I have maintained, then the rest of us should be willing to entertain some questions about our past assumptions too. It is clear Innis’ later work is not ideologically motivated. He
undertook it for his own reasons. He did not need a career boost; if anything,
he took a chance on undermining what he had achieved. His prestige was
high; he had no need or desire to become a cult item in pop culture. There
is nothing in his work that could have been calculated to take advantage
of current trends in media analysis, since he more or less created the
field as he wrote about it. For the same reason, there was no one around
to seize on his work for ulterior motives and use it to their advantage. Let me turn to a reconsideration of the relation between thought and action in this dim light. Hannah Arendt wrote, especially in her final book, The Life of the Mind, about the relation between thinking and the world. I feel comfortable bringing this up since Arendt was devoted to classical civilization, as was Innis. But perhaps all I am really doing is taking two of the writers from whom I have learned a great deal and looking at them in relation to one another. Arendt described the thinking of even classical Greek philosophy as something that took you not away from the world but into it – though not for the purposes of solving problems to be found there. Thinking came about, she said, as a sort of amazement and wonder in response to mere existence; anyone can experience this, and it has implications for acting because it alters the relation between self and world. If you think even of classical philosophical thinking in this manner, not as something that removes the thinker to a realm of eternal verities but as a way of being more intensely in the world, then the sciences and particularly the social sciences do not require overt practical justifications. I think Innis in his later works was moving to a recovery of thinking in that sense, with his admiration for Greece and its Oral Tradition; in the face of the practicality, knowledge mongering, and problem solving that the “positive” sciences, both natural and social, have been prone to since their rise. “To expect truth to come from thinking,” wrote Arendt, “signifies that we mistake the need to think with the urge to know . . . there is nothing more to be said than that life deprived of thought would be meaningless, even though thought will never make men wise or give them the answers to thought’s own questions.” She is speaking about Socrates here, and she says, “The meaning of what Socrates was doing lay in the activity itself. Or to put it differently: to think and to be fully alive are the same, and this implies that thinking must always begin afresh . . .” And, “the only possible metaphor one may conceive of for the life of the mind is the sensation of being alive.” The “inability to think (in this sense) is not a failing of the many who lack brain power but an ever present possibility for everybody – scientists, scholars, and other specialists in mental enterprises not excluded. …A life without thinking is quite possible; it simply fails to develop its own essence – it is not merely meaningless; it is not fully alive. Unthinking men are like sleepwalkers.” I think of Innis as a man determined to awake from the anthropological sleep of the human sciences – of which he had become one of the outstanding practitioners – and not to fall back into it, however strong the temptation or maybe just the force of habit. Thinking in this sense, which Arendt wrote about in her last book and which I believe Innis undertook in his, is a justification in itself, whether it has implications for action, and even policy, or not. In this sense, each person has the opportunity to think uniquely, because of the unique place between past and future that each person occupies. (Once, as a graduate student in philosophy of religion, I told a teacher of mine named Abraham Joshua Heschel that I was thinking of writing a thesis on the neo-Kantian ethics of Hermann Cohen. “It’s been done,” said Heschel. “Not by me,” I said. “I like your answer,” said Heschel.) “For the need to think,” wrote Arendt, “can never be stilled by allegedly definite insights of ‘wise men’; it can be satisfied only through thinking, and the thoughts I had yesterday will satisfy this need today only to the extent that I want and am able to think them anew.” I would like to think the later Innis, in his unique place between past and future, was trying to reoccupy a different, difficult, utterly human space by, as Arendt says, attempting to “reclaim our human dignity, win it back, as it were, from the pseudo-divinity named History of the modern age, without denying history’s importance but denying its right to being the ultimate judge.” As for the connection between thought and action, Arendt says it was when she attended the trial of Adolf Eichmann as a journalist, and noticed the unthinkingness of Eichmann, his ‘banality’ which became the subtitle of her book on him, that she began to wonder about the connection between sheer thinking and the “faculty for telling right from wrong.” She began to consider whether the intellectual (not in a problem solving or academic sense, but in the Socratic sense of the ability to wonder at all things at any time) and the ethical might be related in surprising ways, even whether they might be, in some sense, the same thing. This led to perplexities about a recent book of her own, The Human Condition, in which as a political philosopher she demarcated the vita activa from the vita contemplativa and concentrated solely on the former. She had ended that book in a state of perplexity about the distinction, with a quotation from Cicero, ascribed to Cato, that “never is a man more active than when he does nothing, never is he less alone than when he is by himself.” When she attended the Eichmann trial she was still in a quandary about these relations. She rejects Hegel’s straightforward claim that to think is to act, since acting only happens, she says, in concert with others. So it becomes a matter of trying to think through the complex relations between thinking and acting. (Let me digress to a small example of how this can work. Arendt writes, “it is not through acting but through contemplating” that “the meaning of the whole is revealed. The spectator, not the actor, holds the clue to the meaning of human affairs.” I cannot help but think in this connection of accounts regarding the massive and exhilarating protest march of 2 November 1996 through Toronto, and the complaint I heard from various people that the speeches at the end were a letdown because at that point they wanted someone to say, on behalf of all those who had experienced the day, what it amounted to, and no one did.) I do not think these relations are easy to sort out. The real conclusion is that the relation between thought and action is problematical; they are not separate, and they are not the same; nor are they simply related as two distinct activities, one of which can produce or deduce the other. Anyone who tried to reduce these relations to simple formulae deserves the kind of scorn deployed by Foucault, who heaped contempt on the “profound stupidity” of those (particularly leftists like myself at a certain point, I assume) who “assert that there is no philosophy without political choice, that all thought is either ‘progressive’ or ‘reactionary.’” “Their foolishness,” he said, “is to believe that all thought ‘expresses’ the ideology of a class,” but reluctantly he had to concede their “involuntary profundity” because even in their thickness and mechanical mind set, “they point directly at the modern mode of being of thought.” This mode of being is that “modern thought, from its inception and in its very density, is a certain mode of action . . . it is no longer theoretical. As soon as it functions it offends or reconciles, attracts or repels, breaks, dissociates, unites or reunites; it cannot help but liberate and enslave.” It seems to me this active, influencing, oppressing, liberating, enslaving character of modern thought – certainly in the sense of the sciences but also in a more general sense – tormented Innis and led him to write his final works. Why do we attend to that which we attend? Why do we value or devalue as we do? It is our way of thinking which has led to the collapse of Western civilization and the wars and misery of our age, and there was no easy way out. His investigations of communications and technology were meant at least to illuminate our dilemmas; but there was no assurance mere insight would lead anywhere. There is something familiar about technological determinism, about technomanias
and technophobias, to someone like myself, who felt a connection to Marxism
in the 1960s and after. What else are you going to say about a notion
like “conditions create consciousness”? In fact, when I first
read McLuhan in the 1960s, I quickly assimilated Marxism. “The medium
is the message.” Okay, that is the same as “Conditions create
consciousness” and – Bob’s your uncle. I would have
bridled at being called a technological determinist, “nuanced”
it, posited reciprocal action, and so forth, but I think there would have
been some truth to it. It is the sort of challenge any kind of historical
explanation has to put up with. But what lingers with me from those years
is how important it seemed to us at the time that History was on our side,
that History would absolve us. Was this just a humanely understandable
desire for certain revenge against the brutal forces we were protesting,
and which too often seemed to win? If we had known for certain that History
would not absolve us, that we would not win out, even after death, would
that have been cause to pack it in? I doubt it. You were in the fight
because it was right, not because it was a winner. I would say what that
belief really did was to shield us from despair, in the face of a lot
of evidence to the contrary. But at a cost. The cost was that the whole
thing was rigged. History was in charge, even if human beings had some
role to play; what you were trying to do was figure out your preassigned
role and then play it. In the absence of that assurance, in the post-Cold
War for example, personally I feel liberated from that sense of it all
being rigged. But that too has a cost: we no longer feel confident of
the outcome, and in that lurks the danger of Now it seems to me Innis fought his own battles with despair, based on his sense of history, and the determinations of technology, especially what he saw as the biases of communications; though at least he never had to copy with a sense of loss after discovering history was not on his side. In his grappling with the biases of communication he was not just dealing with specific effects of the succession of technologies from oral to written to print to electronic, but with the historical mentality itself, what Arendt called the pseudo-divinity of History, the spatialization of time, the loss of its values, the fracturing of continuity and community; so for him it was not just a matter of emancipating yourself and your society from some particular effects of history but from the historical mentality itself. This was a pretty notable endeavor for a great historian to take on, but then who better than a great historian to undertake it? Nor was Innis alone in the aspiration. -published in Queen’s Quarterly 104/2 (Summer 1997) 245-5 |
|||