“This should not be very surprising, for psychoanalysis has already
shown us that speech is not merely the medium which manifests—or
dissembles—desire; it is also the object of desire. Similarly,
historians have constantly impressed upon us that speech is no mere
verbalisation of conflicts and systems of domination, but that it is
the very object of man's conflicts. But our society possesses yet another
principle of exclusion; not another prohibition, but a division and
a rejection. I have in mind the opposition: reason and folly.”
(149)
“Of the three great systems of exclusion governing discourse—prohibited
words, the division of madness and the will to truth—I have spoken
at greatest length concerning the third. With good reason: for centuries,
the former have continually tended toward the latter; because this last
has, gradually, been attempting to assimilate the others in order both
to modify them and to provide them with a firm foundation. Because,
if the two former are continually growing more fragile and less certain
to the extent that they are now invaded by the will to truth, the latter,
in contrast, daily grows in strength, in depth and implacability.”
(151)
“True discourse, liberated by the nature of its form from desire
and power, is incapable of recognising the will to truth which pervades
it; and the will to truth, having imposed itself upon us for so long,
is such that the truth it seeks to reveal cannot fail to mask it.”
(151)
“I believe we can isolate another group: internal rules, where
discourse exercises its own control; rules concerned with the principles
of classification, ordering and distribution. It is as though we were
now involved in the mastery of another dimension of discourse: that
of events and chance.” (152)
“I suspect one could find a kind of gradation between different
types of discourse within most societies: discourse "uttered"
in the course of the day and in casual meetings, and which disappears
with the very act which gave rise to it; and those forms of discourse
that lie at the origins of a certain number of new verbal acts, which
are reiterated, transformed or discussed; in short, discourse which
is spoken and remains spoken, indefinitely, beyond its formulation,
and which remains to be spoken.” (152)
“The novelty lies no longer in what is said, but in its reappearance.”
(153)
“I believe there is another principle of rarefaction, complementary
to the first: the author. Not, of course, the author in the sense of
the individual who delivered the speech or wrote the text in question,
but the author as the unifying principle in a particular group of writings
or statements, lying at the origins of their significance, as the seat
of their coherence.” (153)
“The author is he who implants, into the troublesome language
of fiction, its unities, its coherence, its links with reality”
(153)
“Of course, it would be ridiculous to deny the existence of individuals
who write, and invent. But I think that, for some time, at least, the
individual who sits down to write a text, at the edge of which lurks
a possible ¯uvre, resumes the functions of the author. What he
writes and does not write, what he sketches out, even preliminary sketches
for the work, and what he drops as simple mundane remarks, all this
interplay of differences is prescribed by the author-function. It is
from his new position, as an author, that he will fashion—from
all he might have said, from all he says daily, at any time—the
still shaky profile of his oeuvre.” (153)
“The organisation of disciplines is just as much opposed to the
commentary-principle as it is to that of the author. Opposed to that
of the author, because disciplines are defined by groups of objects,
methods, their corpus of propositions considered to be true, the interplay
of rules and definitions, of techniques and tools.”' (153)
“Botany and medicine, like other disciplines, consist of errors
as well as truths, errors that are in no way residuals, of foreign bodies,
but having their own positive functions and their own valid history,
such that their roles are often indissociable from that of the truths.”
(154)
“For a proposition to belong to botany or pathology, it must
fulfil certain conditions, in a stricter and more complex sense than
that of pure and simple truth: at any rate, other conditions. The proposition
must refer to a specific range of objects.” (154)
“It is always possible one could speak the truth in a void; one
would only be in the true, however, if one obeyed the rules of some
discursive "policy" which would have to be reactivated every
time one spoke.” (155)
“Disciplines constitute a system of control in the production
of discourse, fixing its limits through the action of an identity taking
the form of a permanent reactivation of the rules.” (155)
“There is, I believe, a third group of rules serving to control
discourse....This amounts to a rarefaction among speaking subjects:
none may enter into a discourse on a specific subject unless he has
satisfied certain conditions or if he is not, from the outset, qualified
to do so. More exactly, not all areas of discourse are equally open
and penetrable; some are forbidden territory ... while others are virtually
open to the winds and stand, without any prior restrictions, open to
all.” (155)
“Every educational system is a political means of maintaining
or of modifying the appropriation of discourse, with the knowledge and
the powers it carries with it.” (156)
“Western thought has seen to it that discourse be permitted as
little room as possible between thought and words. It would appear to
have ensured that to discourse should appear merely as a certain interjection
between speaking and thinking; that it should constitute thought, clad
in its signs and rendered visible by words or, conversely, that the
structures of language themselves should be brought into play, producing
a certain effect of meaning. Whether it is the philosophy of a founding
subject, a philosophy of originating experience or a philosophy of universal
mediation, discourse is really only an activity, of writing in the first
case, of reading in the second and exchange in the third. This exchange,
this writing, this reading never involve anything but signs. Discourse
thus nullifies itself, in reality, in placing itself at the disposal
of the signifier.” (157-8)
“I believe we must resolve ourselves to accept three decisions
which our current thinking rather tends to resist, and which belong
to the three groups of function I have just mentioned: to question our
will to truth; to restore to discourse its character as an event; to
abolish the sovereignty of the signifier.... One can straight away distinguish
some of the methodological demands they imply. A principle of reversal,
first of all.... Next, then, the principle of discontinuity .... Discourse
must be treated as a discontinuous activity, its different manifestations
sometimes coming together, but just as easily unaware of, or excluding
each other. The principle of specificity declares that a particular
discourse cannot be resolved by a prior system of significations...We
must conceive discourse as a violence that we do to things, or, at all
events, as a practice we impose upon them; it is in this practice that
the events of discourse find the principle of their regularity. The
fourth principle, that of exteriority, holds that we are not to burrow
to the hidden core of discourse, to the heart of the thought or meaning
manifested in it; instead, taking the discourse itself, its appearance
and its regularity, that we should look for its external conditions
of existence, for that which gives rise to the chance series of these
events and fixes its limits.” (158)
“What is significant is that history does not consider an event
without defining the series to which it belongs, without seeking out
the regularity of phenomena and the probable limits of their occurrence,
without enquiring about variations, inflexions and the slope of the
curve, without desiring to know the conditions on which these depend.
History has long since abandoned its attempts to understand events in
terms of cause and effect in the formless unity of some great evolutionary
process, whether vaguely homogeneous or rigidly hierarchised.”
(159)
“In the sense that this slender wedge I intend to slip into the
history of ideas consists not in dealing with meanings possibly lying
behind this or that discourse, but with discourse as regular series
and distinct events, I fear I recognise in this wedge a tiny (odious,
too, perhaps) device permitting the introduction, into the very roots
of thought, of notions of chance, discontinuity and materiality.”
(159-60)
“Criticism analyses the processes of rarefaction, consolidation
and unification in discourse; genealogy studies their formation, at
once scattered, discontinuous and regular.” (161)
“The critical side of the analysis deals with the systems enveloping
discourse; attempting to mark out and distinguish the principles of
ordering, exclusion and rarity in discourse. We might, to play with
our words, say it practises a kind of studied casualness. The genealogical
side of discourse, by way of contrast, deals with series of effective
formation of discourse: it attempts to grasp it in its power of affirmation,
by which I do not mean a power opposed to that of negation, but the
power of constituting domains of objects, in relation to which one can
affirm or deny true or false propositions. Let us call these domains
of objects positivist and , to play on words yet again, let us say that,
if the critical style is one of studied casualness, then the genealogical
mood is one of felicitous positivism.” (162)
“At all events, one thing at least must be emphasised here: that
the analysis of discourse thus understood, does not reveal the universality
of a meaning, but brings to light the action of imposed rarity, with
a fundamental power of affirmation. Rarity and affirmation; rarity,
in the last resort of affirmation—certainly not any continuous
outpouring of meaning, and certainly not any monarchy of the signifier.”
(162)
“And now, let those who are weak on vocabulary, let those with
little comprehension of theory call all this—if its appeal is
stronger than its meaning for them—structuralism.” (162)